Results for 'Daniel H. Stephen'

971 found
Order:
  1.  50
    Hamlet in Purgatory, by Stephen Greenblatt.Daniel H. Strait - 2001 - The Chesterton Review 27 (3):349-353.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  20
    Explorations of Cohen, Dunbar, and McClelland's (1990) connectionist model of Stroop performance.Stephen M. Kanne, David A. Balota, Daniel H. Spieler & Mark E. Faust - 1998 - Psychological Review 105 (1):174-187.
  3. Small-scale societies exhibit fundamental variation in the role of intentions in moral judgment.H. Clark Barrett, Alexander Bolyanatz, Alyssa N. Crittenden, Daniel M. T. Fessler, Simon Fitzpatrick, Michael Gurven, Joseph Henrich, Martin Kanovsky, Geoff Kushnick, Anne Pisor, Brooke A. Scelza, Stephen Stich, Chris von Rueden, Wanying Zhao & Stephen Laurence - 2016 - Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 (17):4688–4693.
    Intent and mitigating circumstances play a central role in moral and legal assessments in large-scale industrialized societies. Al- though these features of moral assessment are widely assumed to be universal, to date, they have only been studied in a narrow range of societies. We show that there is substantial cross-cultural variation among eight traditional small-scale societies (ranging from hunter-gatherer to pastoralist to horticulturalist) and two Western societies (one urban, one rural) in the extent to which intent and mitigating circumstances influence (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  4.  56
    Returning the tables: language affects spatial reasoning.Stephen C. Levinson, Sotaro Kita, Daniel B. M. Haun & Björn H. Rasch - 2002 - Cognition 84 (2):155-188.
  5.  79
    Berkeley and Spinoza.Stephen H. Daniel - 2010 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 135 (1):123-134.
    There is a widespread assumption that Berkeley and Spinoza have little in common, even though early Jesuit critics in France often linked them. Later commentators have also recognized their similarities. My essay focuses on how Berkeley 's comments on the Arnauld-Malebranche debate regarding objective and formal reality and his treatment of god's creation of finite minds within the order of nature relate his theory of knowledge to his doctrine in a way similar to that of Spinoza. On estime souvent que (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  34
    Moral parochialism and contextual contingency across seven societies.Daniel M. T. Fessler, H. Clark Barrett, Martin Kanovsky, Stephen P. Stich, Colin Holbrook, Joseph Henrich, Alexander H. Bolyanatz, Matthew M. Gervais, Michael Gurven, Geoff Kushnick, Anne C. Pisor, Christopher von Rueden & Stephen Laurence - 2015 - Proceedings of the Royal Society; B (Biological Sciences) 282:20150907.
    Human moral judgement may have evolved to maximize the individual's welfare given parochial culturally constructed moral systems. If so, then moral condemnation should be more severe when transgressions are recent and local, and should be sensitive to the pronouncements of authority figures (who are often arbiters of moral norms), as the fitness pay-offs of moral disapproval will primarily derive from the ramifications of condemning actions that occur within the immediate social arena. Correspondingly, moral transgressions should be viewed as less objectionable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7. Introduction.Stephen H. Daniel - 2007 - In Stephen Hartley Daniel (ed.), Reexamining Berkeley's Philosophy. University of Toronto Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  24
    The Philosophy of Ingenuity: Vico on Proto-Philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 1985 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 18 (4):236 - 243.
  9.  31
    George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    This book is a study of the philosophy of the early 18th century Irish philosopher George Berkeley in the intellectual context of his times, with a particular focus on how, for Berkeley, mind is related to its ideas. It does not assume that thinkers like Descartes, Malebranche, or Locke define for Berkeley the context in which he develops his own thought. Instead, he indicates how Berkeley draws on a tradition that informed his early training and that challenges much of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  62
    Edwards, Berkeley, and Ramist Logic.Stephen H. Daniel - 2001 - Idealistic Studies 31 (1):55-72.
    I will suggest that we can begin to see why Edwards and Berkeley sound so much alike by considering how both think of minds or spiritual substances notas things modeled on material bodies but as the acts by which things are identified. Those acts cannot be described using the Aristotelian subject-predicatelogic on which the metaphysics of substance, properties, attributes, or modes is based because subjects, substances, etc. are themselves initially distinguishedthrough such acts. To think of mind as opposed to matter, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  4
    Berkeley's Doctrine of Bodies as Powers.Stephen H. Daniel - forthcoming - Dialogue:1-17.
    Résumé Les discussions autour de George Berkeley rejettent souvent les remarques de ses Notebooks selon lesquelles (1) les corps sont des pouvoirs qui amènent les percepteurs à avoir des pensées et (2) les corps existent même lorsqu'ils ne sont pas perçus. J'ai déjà noté ces affirmations, mais je n'ai pas expliqué comment les corps sont infiniment liés en tant que pensées (à distinguer des idées), et Melissa Frankel traite les corps comme des archétypes perçus individuellement par Dieu, mais n'explique pas (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    Contemporary Continental Thought.Stephen H. Daniel - 2004 - Prentice-Hall.
    A survey with readings in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Aimed at students and scholars interested in an overview of movements in continental philosophy in the past century.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  48
    Doubts and Doubting in Descartes.Stephen H. Daniel - 1978 - Modern Schoolman 56 (1):57-65.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  30
    Objective-format testing in philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 1981 - Metaphilosophy 12 (1):96–112.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Some Conflicting Assumptions of Journalistic Ethics.Stephen H. Daniel - 1992 - In Elliot D. Cohen (ed.), Philosophical Issues in Journalism. Oxford University Press. pp. 50--58.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. The Philosophic Methodology of John Toland.Stephen H. Daniel - 1977 - Dissertation, Saint Louis University
  17. Editor’s Note: The Karlsruhe Conference: Highlights, Prospects.Stephen H. Daniel - 2009 - Berkeley Studies 20:3-4.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  77
    Metaphor in the Historiography of Philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 1986 - Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History 15 (2):191-210.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  36
    Postmodernity, Poststructuralism, and the Historiography of Modern Philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 1995 - International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (3):255-267.
    Well-known for its criticism of totalizing accounts of reason and truth, postmodern thought also makes positive contributions to our understanding of the sensual, ideological, and linguistic contingencies that inform modernist representations of self, history, and the world. The positive side of postmodernity includes structuralism and poststructuralism, particularly as expressed by theorists concerned with practices of the body (Lacan, Foucault, Deleuze), commodity differences (Adorno, Althusser), language (Derrida), and gender (Kristeva, Irigaray). Though these challenges to modernity do not privilege subjectivity, they suggest (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Senior Editor’s Note.Stephen H. Daniel - 2007 - Berkeley Studies 18:2.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  79
    Berkeley on God.Stephen H. Daniel - 2021 - In Samuel Charles Rickless (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 177-93.
    Berkeley’s appeal to a posteriori arguments for God’s existence supports belief only in a God who is finite. But by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. In this latter argument, God is not the efficient cause of particular finite things in the world, for such an explanation does not provide a justification or rationale for why the totality of finite things would exist in the first place. Instead, God is understood as the creator (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  33
    Descartes on Immortality and Animals.Stephen H. Daniel - 2024 - The European Legacy 29 (2):184-198.
    For Descartes, our minds are not natural causes because they are not themselves objects; rather, they are the activities that identify objects. In short, they are our challenges to the natural order of things, both in how we adapt to novel situations (as exhibited in what has been called the “rational action test”) and in how we respond in unexpected yet appropriate ways to linguistic cues (in the “language test”). Because these tests reveal ways in which our minds (as “pure,” (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Berkeley on God's Knowledge of Pain.Stephen H. Daniel - 2018 - In Stefan Storrie (ed.), Berkeley's Three Dialogues: New Essays. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 136-145.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  37
    Myth and Rationality in Mandeville.Stephen H. Daniel - 1986 - Journal of the History of Ideas 47 (4):595-609.
    Bernard Mandeville's early work *Typhon* reveals how his *Fable of the Bees* can be understood not only as an extended commentary of an Aesopic fable but also as a form of mythic writing. The appeal to the mythic in discourse provides him with the opportunity to give both a genetic account of the development of language and social practices and a functional account of the the socializing impact of myths (including classical ones). The artificial distinction between treating Mandeville's writings as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  69
    Vico's historicism and the ontology of arguments.Stephen H. Daniel - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3):431-446.
    Vico's historicist claims (1) that different ages are intelligible only in their own terms and (2) that the certainty and authority of history depend on its narrative formulation seem at odds with his doctrines of ideal eternal history and divine providence. He resolves these issues, however, in his treatment of ideal eternal history by using the distinction between the certain and the true to show how rhetorical expression generates meaning in and as history. Specifically, by appealing to an ontology that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  52
    Descartes' Treatment of 'lumen naturale'.Stephen H. Daniel - 1978 - Studia Leibnitiana 10 (1):92 - 100.
    Descartes’ “natural light” has been interpreted as a faculty of the mind, the sense-imagination-reason-under-standing composite, the principle of intellectual integrity and growth, or even God himself. In Meditations III and IV in particular, the meaning of lumen natural depends on recognizing how light and nature define one another and how “my nature” serves as the basis for pointing to what is beyond the domain of natural reason, including religious faith and natural belief (especially regarding morality).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Teaching Recent Continental Philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 2004 - In Tziporah Kasachkoff (ed.), Teaching Philosophy: Theoretical Reflections and Practical Suggestions. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. pp. 197-206.
    An explanation of how to organize and teach a course in recent continental thought, including treatments of the major figures in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Reprint from *In the Socratic Tradition: Essays on Teaching Philosophy*, ed. Tziporah Kasachkoff (Lanham, Md: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Berkeley's Rejection of Divine Analogy.Stephen H. Daniel - 2011 - Science Et Esprit 63 (2):149-161.
    Berkeley argues that claims about divine predication (e.g., God is wise or exists) should be understood literally rather than analogically, because like all spirits (i.e., causes), God is intelligible only in terms of the extent of his effects. By focusing on the harmony and order of nature, Berkeley thus unites his view of God with his doctrines of mind, force, grace, and power, and avoids challenges to religious claims that are raised by appeals to analogy. The essay concludes by showing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. Berkeley's Christian neoplatonism, archetypes, and divine ideas.Stephen H. Daniel - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2):239-258.
    Berkeley's doctrine of archetypes explains how God perceives and can have the same ideas as finite minds. His appeal of Christian neo-Platonism opens up a way to understand how the relation of mind, ideas, and their union is modeled on the Cappadocian church fathers' account of the persons of the trinity. This way of understanding Berkeley indicates why he, in contrast to Descartes or Locke, thinks that mind (spiritual substance) and ideas (the object of mind) cannot exist or be thought (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  33
    Moral parochialism misunderstood: a reply to Piazza and Sousa.Daniel M. T. Fessler, Colin Holbrook, Martin Kanovsky, H. Clark Barrett, Alexander H. Bolyanatz, Matthew M. Gervais, Michael Gurven, Joseph Henrich, Geoff Kushnick, Anne C. Pisor, Stephen P. Stich, Christopher von Rueden & Stephen Laurence - 2016 - Proceedings of the Royal Society; B (Biological Sciences) 283.
  31.  14
    Beyond the Western Tradition: Readings in Moral and Political Philosophy.Daniel A. Bonevac, William Boon & Stephen H. Phillips - 1992 - McGraw-Hill Humanities, Social Sciences & World Languages.
  32. Berkeley on God's Knowledge of Pain.Stephen H. Daniel - 2018 - In Stefan Storrie (ed.), Berkeley's Three Dialogues: New Essays. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 136-145.
    Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which would require God to have senses, which he does not). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  34
    M. Hobbes and America: Exploring the Constitutional Foundations. [REVIEW]Stephen H. Daniel - 1983 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (3):698-699.
    Though some of the critical reviews of Frank M. Coleman's Hobbes and America have alluded to the affinities of his work to that of Strauss, Macpherson, Laslett, and Oakeshott, most have ignored Coleman's specifically philosophic treatment of Hobbes as the foundational thinker most responsive to political realities which emerge in the seventeenth century and still characterize American politics. Coleman's purpose is to demonstrate how the operative American constitutional philosophy can be recognized clearly only when understood in the context of its (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  82
    Kinship intensity and the use of mental states in moral judgment across societies.Cameron M. Curtin, H. Clark Barrett, Alexander Bolyanatz, Alyssa N. Crittenden, Daniel Fessler, Simon Fitzpatrick, Michael Gurven, Martin Kanovsky, Stephen Laurence, Anne Pisor, Brooke Scelza, Stephen Stich, Chris von Rueden & Joseph Henrich - 2020 - Evolution and Human Behavior 41 (5):415-429.
    Decades of research conducted in Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, & Democratic (WEIRD) societies have led many scholars to conclude that the use of mental states in moral judgment is a human cognitive universal, perhaps an adaptive strategy for selecting optimal social partners from a large pool of candidates. However, recent work from a more diverse array of societies suggests there may be important variation in how much people rely on mental states, with people in some societies judging accidental harms just (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. The ramist context of Berkeley's philosophy.Stephen H. Daniel - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3):487 – 505.
    Berkeley's doctrines about mind, the language of nature, substance, minima sensibilia, notions, abstract ideas, inference, and freedom appropriate principles developed by the 16th-century logician Peter Ramus and his 17th-century followers (e.g., Alexander Richardson, William Ames, John Milton). Even though Berkeley expresses himself in Cartesian or Lockean terms, he relies on a Ramist way of thinking that is not a form of mere rhetoric or pedagogy but a logic and ontology grounded in Stoicism. This article summarizes the central features of Ramism, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  73
    Civility and sociability: Hobbes on man and citizen.Stephen H. Daniel - 1980 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (2):209-215.
  37. Berkeley, Suárez, and the Esse-Existere Distinction.Stephen H. Daniel - 2000 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74 (4):621-636.
    For Berkeley, a thing's existence 'esse' is nothing more than its being perceived 'as that thing'. It makes no sense to ask (with Samuel Johnson) about the 'esse' of the mind or the specific act of perception, for that would be like asking what it means for existence to exist. Berkeley's "existere is percipi or percipere" (NB 429) thus carefully adopts the scholastic distinction between 'esse' and 'existere' ignored by Locke and others committed to a substantialist notion of mind. Following (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38. How Berkeley's Works are Interpreted.Stephen H. Daniel - 2010 - In Silvia Parigi (ed.), George Berkeley: Religion and Science in the Age of Enlightenment. Springer.
    Instead of interpreting Berkeley in terms of the standard way of relating him to Descartes, Malebranche, and Locke, I suggest we consider relating him to other figures (e.g., Stoics, Ramists, Suarez, Spinoza, Leibniz). This allows us to integrate his published and unpublished work, and reveals how his philosophic and non-philosophic work are much more aligned with one another. I indicate how his (1) theory of powers, (2) "bundle theory" of the mind, and (3) doctrine of "innate ideas" are understood in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  51
    The harmony of the Leibniz-Berkeley juxtaposition.Stephen H. Daniel - 2007 - In Pauline Phemister & Stuart Brown (eds.), Leibniz and the English-Speaking World. Springer. pp. 163--180.
  40. Les limites de la philosophie naturelle de Berkeley.Stephen H. Daniel - 2004 - In Sébastien Charles (ed.), Science et épistémologie selon Berkeley. Presses de l’Université Laval. pp. 163-70.
    (Original French text followed by English version.) For Berkeley, mathematical and scientific issues and concepts are always conditioned by epistemological, metaphysical, and theological considerations. For Berkeley to think of any thing--whether it be a geometrical figure or a visible or tangible object--is to think of it in terms of how its limits make it intelligible. Especially in De Motu, he highlights the ways in which limit concepts (e.g., cause) mark the boundaries of science, metaphysics, theology, and morality.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. John R. Roberts. A Metaphysics for the Mob: The Philosophy of George Berkeley. [REVIEW]Stephen H. Daniel - 2007 - Berkeley Studies 18:36-39.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  39
    A philosophical theory of literary continuity and change.Stephen H. Daniel - 1980 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3):275-280.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  59
    Berkeley's Non-Cartesian Notion of Spiritual Substance.Stephen H. Daniel - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4):659-682.
    As central as the notion of mind is for Berkeley, it is not surprising that what he means by mind stirs debate. At issue are questions about not only what kind of thing a mind is but also how we can know it. This convergence of ontological and epistemological interests in discussing mind has led some commentators to argue that Berkeley's appeal to the Cartesian vocabulary of 'spiritual substance' signals his appropriation of elements of Descartes's theory of mind. But in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  23
    Berkeley's Semantic Treatment of Representation.Stephen H. Daniel - 2008 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 25 (1):41 - 55.
  45.  54
    Descartes on Myth and Ingenuity / Ingenium.Stephen H. Daniel - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):157-170.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  15
    Incoming Editor’s Note.Stephen H. Daniel - 2006 - Berkeley Studies 17:3.
    A quick introduction to my becoming the editor of *Berkeley Studies* in 2006.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  23
    Myth and the Grammar of Discovery in Francis Bacon.Stephen H. Daniel - 1982 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 15 (4):219 - 237.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  39
    Paramodern Strategies of Philosophical Historiography.Stephen H. Daniel - 1993 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (1):41-63.
  49.  42
    Substance and Person: Berkeley on Descartes and Locke.Stephen H. Daniel - 2018 - Ruch Filozoficzny 74 (4):7.
    In his post-1720 works, Berkeley focuses his comments about Descartes on mechanism and about Locke on general abstract ideas. He warns against using metaphysical principles to explain observed regularities, and he extends his account to include spiritual substances (including God). Indeed, by calling a substance a spirit, he emphasizes how a person is simply the will that ideas be differentiated and associated in a certain way, not some <i>thing</i> that engages in differentiation. In this sense, a substance cannot be conceived (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  45
    The Narrative Character of Myth and Philosophy in Vico.Stephen H. Daniel - 1988 - International Studies in Philosophy 20 (1):1-9.
1 — 50 / 971